Consider the following statements:

It is essential to singleton Socrates that it have Socrates as a member.

By metaphysical necessity, there is a first moment in time.

It is a law of metaphysics that any two objects compose another object.

According to these statements, the embedded claims—the prejacents—enjoy a certain ‘robust’, not merely accidental, status: the status of pertaining to the essence of some entity, holding with metaphysical necessity, or being a metaphysical law, respectively.Footnote 1 Let us, borrowing terminology from Kappes (2020), call the truths expressed by true such statements ‘status truths’. Apart from the cases mentioned, the category of status truths also includes truths regarding logical and natural necessity, as well as logical and natural laws.

Status truths are factive: in all cases in which a status truth holds, so does its prejacent. But more than that: many philosophers have been drawn to the idea that status truths do not merely correlate with the truth of their prejacents, but explain them.Footnote 2 And indeed, our explanatory practises seem to accord with this idea. If asked ‘Why is it that singleton Socrates contains Socrates?’, one natural response seems to be: ‘That is just what singleton Socrates is–it has Socrates as a member by its very essence’. When confronted with the question ‘Why is there a first moment in time?’ some philosophers may feel tempted to reply ‘Well, it just could not have been otherwise, there simply has to be a first moment in time’. And a metaphysician who countenances universal composition as a law of metaphysics may want to answer ‘because it is a law of metaphysics that any objects do so’ when called upon to explain how it comes that her laptop and cat compose another object. Assuming that status truths explain their prejacents, the natural next step is then to understand these explanations in terms of ground. After all, the relevant explanations look distinctively metaphysical in character, and grounding-explanations are commonly taken to be paradigmatic cases of metaphysical explanations. Putting these considerations together, we arrive at the principle Ground by Status. According to this principle, status truths ground their prejacents and if the prejacents are universally quantified (such as in the case of the law of universal composition), also instances of their prejacents.Footnote 3

Surely, Ground by Status is not the only way to go in reaction to the example cases. For one thing, one could postulate additional forms of metaphysical explanation distinct from ground, an option explored by Glazier (2017a), Glazier (2017b) and Kappes (2020), Kappes (2021). And for another, one could contest the view that the example cases correspond to genuine explanations. Going that route, one might e.g. hold that the answers in the cases correspond merely to ways to reject the need for explanation, or that they provide some of what we desire from explanations—such as surprise reduction—while falling short of providing proper explanations.Footnote 4 But while Ground by Status is not the only option, it is the natural default theory of the explanatory role of status truths, and comes with various theoretical benefits. It offers a particularly straightforward, simple and uniform account of the example cases. It can account for the fact that status truths are factive, and even necessarily so, in in a smooth and natural way. For given that grounds necessitate what they ground, the necessitation of prejacents by the status truths immediately follows. And Ground by Status does not demand the introduction of any novel resources, but makes do with the well researched notion of grounding.

Glazier and Kappes have recently made a forceful and highly general case against Ground by Status, however. They think that Ground by Status has to be rejected for all kinds of status-truths: for essence-truths (Glazier, 2017a; Kappes, 2020), necessity-truths (Glazier, 2017b; Kappes, 2020), and law-truths (Kappes, 2020, 2021). One argument that plays a crucial role in both Glazier’s and Kappes’s case against Ground by Status is an objection that I shall label ‘the argument from the logic of ground’, or, for short, ‘the LG-argument’. The gist of this objection is that, granting the existence of plausible candidates for status truths, Ground by Status violates an intuitively plausible and widely held view: that any ground for a disjunction has to be ‘mediated through’ the disjuncts, in a sense to be specified later on.Footnote 5

My aim in this paper is to defend Ground by Status against this argument. I start out by presenting the LG-argument in some more detail (§1). I then show that, on closer examination, the principle about the grounds of disjunctions that the LG-argument rests upon is incompatible with a worldly conception of ground, viz., a conception on which grounding is purely sensitive to how the world is in itself, independent of the way in which we represent it. Hence, for the LG-argument to succeed, a case would need to be made that Ground by Status has to be understood in terms of the alternative representational conception of ground, according to which ground is also sensitive to our representational guises. But there are no good reasons to think that a representational construal of Ground by Status is mandatory. Thus, proponents of Ground by Status should construe it as a principle about worldly grounding, escaping the LG Argument (§2).

1 The argument from the logic of ground

To remain neutral on the question of whether grounding is to be understood as a relation between entities, I will take grounding claims to be officially regimented in terms of a sentential operator ‘<’. Here, ‘\(A < B\)’ may be approximated by formulations such as ‘its being the case that A makes it the case that B’ or ‘B because A’ in natural language. Despite officially using the operationalist framework, I shall often nevertheless speak as if grounding was a relation between truths (‘A grounds B’ and the likes) to facilitate formulations in natural language. I presume a factive understanding of ground, i.e., one on which for ‘\(A <B\)’ to be true, both ‘A’ and ‘B’ have to be true. Moreover, I shall use the word ‘ground’ in the sense of ‘strict, full ground’, as opposed to ‘weak/partial ground’.Footnote 6

As anticipated in the introduction, the goal of the LG-argument is to show that Ground by Status contradicts a plausible and influential view on the grounds of disjunctions: the view that, to borrow Kit Fine’s (2012a) phrase, any ground of a disjunction has to be ‘mediated through’ its true disjuncts. The thought is this. When investigating into the grounds of disjunctions, a natural starting point is that disjunctions are grounded in their true disjuncts. For instance, the truth that Barcelona is in Spain or Barcelona is in Antarctica is grounded in the truth that Barcelona is in Spain, and the truth that it is sunny or it is cloudy is grounded in, say, the truth that it is sunny. Yet the demand that disjunctions should be exclusively grounded in their true disjuncts is too strong and needs to be loosened. Thus, to avoid violations of the transitivity of grounding, one should also countenance the grounds of true disjuncts as grounds of disjunctions. And indeed, following Fine (2012ab), one may think that a disjunction can also be grounded in truths which stand neither in a relationship of identity nor of ground to one of the disjuncts, but something which, to put it crudely, also encompasses cases ‘in between’ the two. The idea here is that there might be cases in which one truth is distinct, but so closely connected to another truth that the former truth can do all the grounding-work of the latter truth: whatever the latter truth can ground, the former can too. To give an example, one might think that the truth that the cat is on the mat is so closely related to the truth that the mat is under the cat that the former can ground whatever the latter can ground. Let us say that in such cases, the former truth ‘subsumes the grounding-work’ of the latter truth. That is, A subsumes the grounding-work of B iff, for any \(C_1, C_2,...\) and D, if \(B, C_1, C_2,....\) ground D, then \(A, C_1, C_2,...\) ground D.Footnote 7 Note that, given this definition, any truth automatically subsumes the grounding-work of itself and given the transitivity of grounding, any truth that grounds another truth also subsumes the grounding-work of this truth. So we can state the condition directly in terms of grounding-work subsumption. Finally, there is a further option that one may additionally want to countenance: that disjunctions can also be grounded in truths that ground the conjunction of their true disjuncts. Adopting all of these ideas, we obtain:

Disjunctions: If B grounds \(A_1 \vee A_2\) then either (a) \(A_1\) is true and B subsumes the grounding-work of \(A_1\), or (b) \(A_2\) is true and B subsumes the grounding-work of \(A_2\), or (c) \(A_1 \& A_2\) is true and B grounds \(A_1 \& A_2\).Footnote 8

As Glazier notes, Disjunctions follows from the elimination rule for disjunctions in Fine’s (2012a) influential logic for grounding. And indeed, various other logics of grounding that have been suggested later on accord with the principle (see Correia (2017a, 2018, deRosset and Fine (2022), Krämer (2018, 2019)).Footnote 9Prima facie, there are thus strong reasons to adopt Disjunctions: it is suggested by intuitive considerations when trying to precisify the idea that the grounds for disjunctions have to be mediated via their disjuncts, and it is backed up by its incorporation into these broader formal theories.

The goal of the LG-argument is now to show that, in the presence of Disjunctions, Ground by Status conflicts with plausible example cases of status truths with disjunctive prejacents. In the case of essence, the argument can be illustrated on Glazier’s example of a specific Boolean variable foo in a computer program. foo has essentially value 0 or value 1. But it has neither one of these values essentially—if the data input in the program differed, foo could have a different value than it actually has, and foo changes it value over the course of time, or so we may assume. To fix ideas, let us assume that foo actually has value 1. Now, combining Disjunctions and Ground by Essence (the restriction of Ground by Status to the case of essence), a conflict arises in the case of foo. Letting ‘\(\Box _{a}\)’ stand for ‘it is essential to a that’, we have:

(E) \(\Box _{\texttt{foo }}\) (foo has value 0 or foo has value 1).

By Ground by Essence, (E) grounds:

(D) foo has value 0 or foo has value 1.

Disjunctions in turn dictates that (E) subsumes the grounding-work of the true disjunct, viz., of:

(D1) foo has value 1.

But this cannot be the case. For (D1) grounds, among others, contingent truths, such as plausibly the following one:

(D1\('\)) foo has value 1 or Biden is US president in 2022.

If (E) were to subsume the grounding-work of (D1), it would thus have to ground (D1\('\)) as well. Given that grounds necessitate what they ground, however, whatever is grounded in a necessary truth will be itself necessary. And in consequence, necessary truths such as (E) can never ground contingent truths such as (D1\('\)).Footnote 10 In other possible worlds in which foo has value 0 and someone else is US president in 2022, (E) still obtains, but (D1\('\)) does not—which would, if (E) were to ground (D1\('\)), violate grounding necessitarianism.

Abstracting away from the case of foo and essence, the LG-argument can be seen as having the following general form:

  1. (P1)

    Disjunctions.

  2. (P2)

    There are cases of status-truths of the relevant type with a disjunctive prejacent, such that none of the disjuncts is (metaphysically/naturally) necessarily true.

  3. (P3)

    Status truths of the relevant type are (metaphysically/naturally) necessarily true, and grounds (metaphysically/naturally) necessitate what they ground.

    \(\therefore\) The relevant type of Ground by Status is false.

Let us make a number of common assumptions: that the laws of logic/metaphysics/nature are logically/metaphysically/naturally necessary, respectively; that essence entails metaphysical necessity; and that logical necessity entails metaphysical necessity, which in turn entails natural necessity. Then, the argument can be run in terms natural necessity in the cases of Ground by Natural Necessity and Ground by Natural Law, and with either natural or metaphysical necessity in all the other cases. And we can use the case of foo not only in an argument against Ground by Essence, but also in an argument against Ground by Metaphysical Necessity and Ground by Natural Necessity. A further example offered by both Glazier and Kappes is the law of excluded middle, according to which, for any p, \(p \vee \lnot p\). This law serves as an example in the case of Ground by Logical Law, and suitable instances of it serve as examples in the cases of Ground by Logical/Metaphysical/Natural Necessity. However, the cases of Ground by Metaphysical Law and Ground by Natural Law are still remaining. And these cases are trickier—there are no example cases offered in the literature, and I do not have convincing cases to offer either.Footnote 11 So I will have to leave the question of whether the LG-argument applies to these forms of Ground by Status open here.

2 Against the argument from the logic of ground

In the remainder of the paper, my aim will be to challenge the LG-argument against Ground by Status. My objection will neither touch upon the relevant example cases, which I find myself plausible, nor on the modal principles employed in the argument, which I am happy to grant. Instead, my only target in what follows will be the principle Disjunctions. For while, at first glance, this principle enjoys a high degree of intuitive appeal and theoretical support, at second glance, there are independently motivated reasons to resist it.

In a nutshell, the argument will be this. On closer examination, the principle Disjunctions turns out to be incompatible with a natural and popular conception of grounding, according to which grounding is a worldly phenomenon. Disjunctions is only compatible with the alternative representational conception of grounding. But there are no good reasons to think that proponents of Ground by Status should conceive of grounding along representational rather than worldly lines, and thus the LG-argument fails to make a convincing case against Ground by Status.

The argument will proceed in a number of steps. To start, let us assume that Emma, Chris and Mary are cups on my kitchen shelf that are emerald, crimson and maroon all-over, respectively. Now consider the following grounding claim:

(G) Emma is white or Chris is crimson < Emma is white or (Chris is crimson or Mary is white).

This grounding claim is incompatible with Disjunctions. For, according to Disjunctions, (G) could only be true if the putative ground, viz.,

(1) Emma is white or Chris is crimson,

were to subsume the grounding-work of the true disjunct of the groundee, viz.:

(2) Chris is crimson or Mary is white.

And this cannot be the case. For (2) grounds truths that (1) does not ground, such as, plausibly:

(2\('\)) (Chris is crimson or Mary is white) or Biden is US-president in 2022.

To see this, we can draw again on the consideration that grounds necessitate what they ground. For, clearly, (1) fails to necessitate (2\('\)). In worlds in which, say, Emma and Chris are both white, Mary is maroon and the US-president in 2022 is Sanders, (1) will still be true, but (2’) will not. So (G) is incompatible with Disjunctions.

But now, consider the following plausible grounding claim which is in perfect harmony with Disjunctions:

(G*) Emma is white or Chris is crimson < (Emma is white or Chris is crimson) or Mary is white.

The only difference between (G*) and (G) consists in the way in which the sentence-atoms are arranged in terms of brackets. Starting from the groundee in the case of (G*), we can arrive at the one in (G) simply by moving the brackets. Hence, if (G*) is true but (G) is false, this operation fails to preserve ground-theoretic role. Let us say that A and B are ground-theoretically equivalent if they play the same ground-theoretic role, viz., ground the same truths and are grounded in the same truths.Footnote 12 We can thus see that, in order to endorse Disjunctions, one has to reject the following principle:

G-Associativity: For any A, B and C: \((A \vee B) \vee C\) and \(A \vee (B \vee C)\) are ground-theoretically equivalent.

However, there are reasons to think that, for it to be the case that \((A\vee B) \vee C\) just is for it to be the case that \(A \vee (B \vee C)\). That is, the difference between any sentence of the form \((A\vee B) \vee C\) and the corresponding sentence of the form \(A \vee (B \vee C)\) is plausibly a purely representational one. While the two sentences differ with regard to their syntactical form, they still express the same ‘chunk of reality out there’: they represent reality as being the very same way, only under different representational guises. Let us say that A and B are worldly equivalent if for A to be the case just is for B to be the case in this sense.Footnote 13 Then, the claim can be expressed as follows:

W-Associativity: For any A, B and C: \((A\vee B) \vee C\) and \(A \vee (B \vee C)\) are worldly equivalent.

In the recent literature, there has been a surge of interest in the ‘just is’-idiom, and various accounts of it have been proposed (see e.g. Bacon and Dorr (forthcoming), Brast-McKie (2021); Correia (2010), Correia (2016); Dorr (2016); Elgin (forthcoming); Linnebo (2014); Rayo (2013)). These accounts depart from various different theoretical starting points and arrive at substantially different logics governing the idiom. Yet all of these accounts are in agreement that for it to be the case that \((A\vee B) \vee C\) just is for it to be the case that \(A \vee (B \vee C)\). In order to reject this principle, one needs to uphold an extremely fine-grained view on reality—which, once properly spelled out, notoriously threatens to lead us into the Russell-Myhill paradox.Footnote 14 While offering a proper assessment of W-Associativity is beyond the scope of this paper, I take there to be strong prima facie reasons in its favor and I shall assume it in what follows.

Provided that W-Associativity holds, however, it directly follows that, in order to reject G-Associativity, one has to maintain that worldly equivalent truths can still come apart with regard to their ground-theoretic roles. That is, one has to reject:

Worldliness of Ground: Worldly equivalence implies ground-theoretical equivalence.

Thus, in the presence of W-Associativity, proponents of Disjunctions cannot uphold a view on which grounding is purely sensitive to what reality is like in itself. Instead, they are forced to endorse a more fine-grained view on which grounding is also sensitive to the particular ways in which we conceptualize reality.

Following the common terminology of the debate on grounding, let us call a conception of grounding that countenances Worldliness of Ground a ‘worldly conception’ of grounding, and a conception that does not a ‘representational’ (or ‘conceptualist’) conception of grounding.Footnote 15 Accounts of grounding that either explicitly state that they concern a worldly conception of grounding or which incorporate grounding-principles that plausibly correspond to a worldly conception include (Audi 2012a, b; Correia (2010, forthcoming); Correia and Skiles (2019); Fine (2012a, 2012b (semantic side), 2017a; and Lovett (2020). Accounts of grounding that correspond to a representational conception include Correia (2017a, 2017b, 2018; deRosset and Fine (2022); Fine (2012a)b (proof-theoretic side); Krämer (2018), 2019; Rosen (2010); and Schnieder (2010).Footnote 16

To be perfectly clear, an account of grounding counts as representational iff it holds that some purely representational feature or other is relevant for difference in ground-theoretic status. But this does not mean that proponents of a representational conception need to conceive of all representational features as relevant for ground-theoretic status. And thus, although virtually all extant accounts of representational grounding do conceive of the arrangement of brackets as relevant for ground-theoretic status and reject G-Associativity, they need not do so.Footnote 17 My point here is thus merely that, if an account of grounding is worldly, it has to endorse G-Associativity on pain of having to give up on W-Associativity, not that only worldly accounts may endorse this principle,Footnote 18

Let me further illustrate the distinction between worldly and representational grounding by some example cases. On a worldly conception of grounding, the following three grounding claims are arguably plausible:

(G2) Emma is emerald or Chris is crimson < Emma is green or Chris is red.

(G3) Emma is emerald or Chris is crimson < Something is emerald or crimson.

(G4) Something in emerald < Something is green.

On representational accounts that incorporate Disjunctions, by contrast, these claims turn out to be problematic.Footnote 19 (G2) proves incompatible with Disjunctions, following a reasoning parallel to the one in the case of (G). And (G3) and (G4) would be ruled out by a principle analogous to Disjunctions for the case of existential generalizations, according to which the only grounds for existential generalizations are (conjunctions of) truths that subsume the grounding-work of instances plus possibly totality truths.Footnote 20

But there are also grounding claims where the situation is reversed: claims that are plausible on a representational conception of grounding but are problematic on a worldly conception. Thus, on a representational conception, it is commonplace to maintain that every true disjunction is grounded in each of its true disjuncts, and every true conjunction in all its conjuncts taken together. And, as limiting cases, this yields:

(G5) Emma is emerald < Emma is emerald and Emma is emerald.

(G6) Emma is emerald < Emma is emerald or Emma is emerald.

On a worldly conception, by contrast, these two claims are arguably to be rejected. For, plausibly, in both claims, the sentences expressing ground and groundee represent reality as being in the same way and merely differ with regard to their representational guises. Hence, on pain of getting violations of the irreflexivity of grounding, the proponent of worldly grounding should reject the idea that every true disjunction is grounded in its true disjuncts and every true conjunction in its conjuncts taken together. Instead, she would uphold restricted versions of these principles that exclusively concern standard cases in which, to put it crudely, the disjuncts/conjuncts are suitably ‘disconnected’.Footnote 21

With these considerations in place, let us now return to the case of Ground by Status. As we have seen, the situation is this. The LG-argument against Ground by Status rests on Disjunctions. In order to endorse Disjunctions, one has to reject G-Associativity. But making plausible assumptions about worldly equivalence, G-Associativity is mandatory on a worldly conception on grounding. Hence, the LG-argument can only be sustained on a representational conception of grounding, but not on a worldly one. And thus, in order for the LG-argument to succeed, it would need to be shown that Ground by Status has to be interpreted in terms of representational as opposed to worldly grounding.Footnote 22

But it is hard to see how such an argument might go. Thus, arguably, the only situations where the representational conception of grounding would be mandatory would be ones in which ground and groundee are worldly equivalent, such as, on certain views, cases in which the grounds provide us with a metaphysical analysis/real definition of the groundee (Correia (2017b); Rosen (2015); Skiles (2014)). And the case of Ground by Status is clearly not one of these cases. For, in the case of Ground by Status, ground and groundee are not worldly equivalent: it is not the case that for foo to have essentially value 0 or value 1 just is for it to have value 0 or value 1; or that for there to be necessarily a first point in time just is for there to be a first point in time; or that for it to be law of nature that objects attract each other with this-and-that force just is for objects to attract each other with this-and-that force, and so on. The relevant status truths demand something of reality that goes beyond what their prejacents do, and they are thus not worldly equivalent to them. Proponents of Ground by Status are thus under no pressure to adopt a representational construal of their principle.

And indeed, the construal of Ground by Status in terms of worldly grounding is not merely a legitimate, but a very natural one: as a claim regarding the objective structure of reality in itself, independent of our representational guises. But, as we have seen, as soon as Ground by Status is interpreted in this way, Disjunctions becomes untenable and Ground by Status immune to the LG-argument. And importantly, the rejection of Disjunctions for Ground by Status on the basis of these considerations is not an ad hoc move, with the only purpose of saving Ground by Status. Instead, the move is independently motivated by the natural and popular thought that (at least one type of) grounding corresponds to a purely worldly relationship. All in all, rejecting Disjunctions on the basis of the worldly vs. representational distinction is an independently motivated and plausible way of blocking the LG-argument. Proponents of Ground by Status should construe it as a principle about worldly grounding, escaping the LG-argument.