Skip to main content
Log in

Grasp and scientific understanding: a recognition account

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

To understand why a phenomenon occurs, it is not enough to possess a correct explanation of the phenomenon: you must grasp the explanation. In this formulation, “grasp” is a placeholder, standing for the psychological or epistemic relation that connects a mind to the explanatory facts in such a way as to produce understanding. This paper proposes and defends an account of the “grasping” relation according to which grasp of a property (to take one example of the sort of entity that turns up in explanations) is a matter of recognitional ability: roughly, a property is grasped to the extent to which the would-be understander is capable of recognizing instances of the property.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Opinion might well be divided as to whether the student has any grasp of effective population whatsoever. The recognition approach developed in this paper takes a liberal view; they do have a little, and in particular they have more than the many people who have never heard of effective population.

  2. This case should be distinguished from one in which the student has mastered simple Newtonian physics, placing the passive third-law forces even in novel scenarios, but has no further explanatory story about the underpinnings of the passive forces, for example, no explanation of rigidity in solid objects. That, of course, was the situation of Newton himself. I am not claiming a deficit of grasp here.

  3. Arguably, passive third-law forces are such a case: in a full-dress Newtonian physics, there are no passive forces; rather, all forces are consequences of force laws such as the law of gravity that implicitly conform to the third law of motion. The third law is thus to be understood not as a separate physical principle but as a constraint on force laws.

  4. For these and other philosophically interesting varieties of understanding in everyday life and science, see Kvanvig (2003), Baumberger et al. (2017), and Grimm (2021).

  5. There is—perhaps needless to say—a strong connection between a recognition approach to grasp and various recognitional approaches to the nature of representation, running from causal covariance theories (Fodor 1990) to what Evans (1982) called “Russell’s principle”, the precept that in order to think about a thing, you must be able to distinguish it from other things.

  6. Having multiple methods for recognizing an instance may, however, enhance accuracy, thereby augmenting grasp along the other dimension.

  7. Likewise, according to the knowledge-based approach, grasp-constituting information is not limited to facts that have some recognitional use.

  8. Understanding that term to refer, in such cases, to oxygen, as suggested by Kitcher (1993).

  9. More carefully: in circumstances in which the terms of the theory refer and the statements framed using those terms are true.

References

  • Baumberger, C., C. Beisbart, and G. Brun. (2017). What is understanding? An overview of recent debates in epistemology and philosophy of science. In S. R. Grimm, C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New perspectives from epistemology and philosophy of science. Routledge.

  • Brandom, R. (2009). Reason in philosophy: Animating ideas. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (2017). Understanding scientific understanding. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (1996). Considered judgment. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R. (2014). Understanding as knowledge of causes. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue epistemology naturalized: Bridges between virtue epistemology and philosophy of science. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R., (2021). Understanding. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Summer 2021 edition. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/understanding/.

  • Hannon, M. (2021). Recent work in the epistemology of understanding. American Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 269–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hills, A. (2016). Understanding why. Noûs, 50, 661–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1992). Lectures on logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2015). Understanding phenomena. Synthese, 192, 3799–3816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2017). Understanding, explanation, and scientific knowledge. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Le Bihan, S. (2017). Enlightening falsehoods: A modal view of scientific understanding. In S. R. Grimm, C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New perspectives from epistemology and philosophy of science (pp. 293–317). Routledge.

  • Lipton, P. (2009). Understanding without explanation. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 43–63). University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, M. (2012). An inferential model of scientific understanding. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2010). Knowledge and understanding. In The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riaz, A. (2015). Moral understanding and knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 172, 113–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L. and J. Woodward. (2023). Causal approaches to scientific explanation. In E. N. Zalta and U. Nodelman (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Spring 2023 edition. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/causal-explanation-science/.

  • Sliwa, P. (2015). Understanding and knowing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 115(1), 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2013). No understanding without explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 510–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, E. (2018). Understanding: Not know-how. Philosophical Studies, 175, 221–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2013). Understanding as representation manipulability. Synthese, 190, 997–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. and L. Ross. (2021). Scientific explanation. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Summer 2021 edition. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/scientificexplanation/

  • Zagzebski, L. (2001). Recovering understanding. In M. Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty: essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I have benefited greatly from the opportunity to present this material, in various incarnations, to audiences at the University of Michigan, New York University, the University of Oxford, Princeton University, and the online Understanding Working Group organized out of UCSD, and at the following events: “Explanation Across the Disciplines” at Middlebury College, “Understanding, in Science and Beyond” at the University of Iceland (online), the SURe IV conference at Fordham University, “Understanding Progress and Progress in Understanding” at the University of Iceland, and “Philosophy Meets Science” at NYU Shanghai. Thanks to Johann Frick for the case of the art forger, and to all of those who commented so perspicuously and so productively on my ideas.

Funding

No funding.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Strevens.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Strevens, M. Grasp and scientific understanding: a recognition account. Philos Stud 181, 741–762 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02121-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02121-x

Keywords

Navigation