Skip to main content
Log in

Knowledge, true belief, and the gradability of ignorance

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Given the significant exculpatory power that ignorance has when it comes to moral, legal, and epistemic transgressions, it is important to have an accurate understanding of the concept of ignorance. According to the Standard View of factual ignorance, a person is ignorant that p whenever they do not know that p, while on the New View, a person is ignorant that p whenever they do not truly believe that p. On their own though, neither of these accounts explains how ignorance can often be a degreed notion—how we can sometimes be slightly ignorant, quite ignorant, or completely ignorant that p. In this paper, I will argue that there is a route for advocates of the Standard View and the New View to accommodate the gradability of ignorance. On the view I defend, ‘ignorant’ picks out everyone that is ignorant to some degree, making it possible that ignorance can be both degreed and characterized as a lack of knowledge or true belief. Even though we can be ignorant to a greater or lesser extent, the only way to avoid being ignorant that p is to know or truly believe.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Rosen (2003).

  2. See Husak (2016)

  3. See Fricker (2016) and Piovarchy (2021). For others who have defended the view that ignorance can serve as a legitimate excuse, either eliminating or greatly reducing a person’s blameworthiness for moral and legal transgressions, see Baron (2016), Fischer and Ravizza (1998), Kelly (2012), and Peels (2014). As suggested by Rosen’s account, the exculpatory power of ignorance disappears if we intentionally remain ignorant. For work on willful ignorance, see Husak and Callender (2010), Lynch (2016), Sarch (2018, 2019), Wieland (2017), and Zimmerman (2020), and for work on culpable ignorance more generally, see FitzPatrick (2008), Robichaud (2014), and Smith (1983).

  4. See Fine (2018), p. 4032. Others who adopt the Standard View include Blome-Tillman (2016), p. 96; Le Morvan (2011a, 2011b, 2012, 2013, 2019); Lynch (2016), p. 509; Unger (1975), p. 93; and Zimmerman (1988), p. 75, and (2008), p. xi.

  5. For the purposes of this paper, I will assume that knowledge is not gradable. For positions on which knowledge can be gradable, however, see Hetherington (2001, 2011) and Sosa (2001, 2009, 2011).

  6. See Ryle (1949), p. 59.

  7. See Dretske (1981), p. 363. This thought, that factual knowledge does not come in degrees, has been used to defend various accounts of knowing that and knowing how. Using the premise that factual knowledge is not gradable, Ryle (1949) has argued that knowing how cannot be reduced to knowing that, while Jason Stanley (2004, 2005) has argued that knowledge contextualists cannot motivate their views by comparing the contextual variability of knowledge to the context-sensitivity of gradable expressions.

  8. See Brogaard (2016), p. 57.

  9. See Goldman and Olsson (2009), p. 21. Advocates of the New View include Goldman (1986), p. 26, and (1999), p. 5; Guerrero (2007), p. 63; Peels (2010), (2011), (2012), and (2014); and van Woudenberg (2009), p. 375.

  10. The Standard View and the New View are not the only accounts of ignorance. Brogaard’s objection may also cause problems for more recent understandings of ignorance, like Piedrahita’s (2021) access view or Silva and Siscoe’s (2024) awareness account, but because the Standard View and the New View are the most popular accounts of ignorance, those are the views which I will focus on here. For more on how the gradability objection affects Pritchard (2021a, 2021b) and Meylan’s (2020, 2024) views that ignorance is a failure of inquiry though, see Sect. 2.

  11. Another route for responding to Brogaard’s criticism is to appeal to contextualism about knowledge, arguing that ‘know’ is context-sensitive in ways that mirror the context sensitivity of ‘ignorant’. If this is right, then a distinct way to reconcile the gradability of ignorance with the Standard View would be to argue that knowledge and ignorance shift together across contexts. Because I’m persuaded that ‘ignorant’ is a partial absolute gradable adjective rather than a relative gradable adjective, however, I do not pursue this strategy here. Thank you to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this possible solution to Brogaard’s challenge.

  12. Some authors use ‘propositional ignorance’ to refer to what I have described as ‘facutal ignorance’, but I take them to be importantly distinct. In his work on ignorance, Le Morvan (2011b, 2012, 2013) distinguishes between ignorance of the content of a proposition and ignorance of a fact. In the first case, a person lacks a concept that prevents them from understanding the proposition in the first place, while in the second case, they understand the proposition even if they do not know whether it obtains.

  13. For more on the various types of ignorance, see Kyle (2021), Le Morvan and Peels (2016), Nottelmann (2016), and Silva and Siscoe (2024).

  14. See Pritchard (2021a, 2021b) and Meylan (2020, 2024).

  15. See Pritchard (2021b), pp. 237–238.

  16. See Unger (1975), p. 175, and Brogaard (2016), p. 58.

  17. See Areddy (2010), Dunning (2016), and Hooke (2021).

  18. See Lynch (2016), p. 511; Peels (2014), p. 479; and Wieland (2017), p. 106.

  19. Though for philosophers who have thought that factual ignorance is not gradable, see Nottelmann (2016), p. 52, and Olsson and Proietti (2016), p. 85.

  20. See Bamford (2005), Bianculli (2020), Boteach (2016), Clarke (2018), Jones (2017), Keertana (2012), and Usher (2014).

  21. See Brogaard (2016), p. 69–70. Brogaard’s official position is that ‘ignorant’ is a “moderately relative gradable adjective”, a term which she coins to distinguish some of the properties of ‘ignorant’ from other relative gradable adjectives. The differences between relative gradable adjectives and moderately relative gradable adjectives, however, will not be relevant for the arguments I make in this paper, so I will stick to the received terminology.

  22. Those who pioneered the distinction between relative and absolute gradable adjectives include Kennedy (2007), Kennedy and McNally (2005), and Rusiecki (1985). For more recent work on the relative/absolute distinction, see Burnett (2014, 2017).

  23. Those who hold that gradable adjectives makes use of a standard of comparison include Barker (2002), Bartsch and Vennemann (1972), Bierwisch (1989), Cresswell (1977), Fine (1975), Kamp (1975), Klein (1980), Lewis (1970), Pinkal (1995), Sapir (1944), and Wheeler (1972), while those who specifically argue that an object must “stand out” relative to the contextual threshold include Rotstein and Winter (2004), Kennedy (2007), and Kennedy and McNally (2005).

  24. For linguists who motivate and employ the “point to” test, see Kennedy (2007), Kyburg and Morreau (2000), Sedivy et al. (1999), and Syrett et al., (2006, 2010).

  25. A key contributor to the distinction between total and partial AAs is Rotstein and Winter (2004).

  26. For examples of the ‘slightly’ test, see Bylinina (2012), Kennedy (2007), Rotstein and Winter (2004), and Solt (2012).

  27. Those who employ the entailment test to distinguish between types of gradable adjectives include Kennedy (2007), Kennedy and McNally (2005), and Rotstein and Winter (2004).

  28. For more work on relative and absolute gradable adjectives in epistemology, see Beddor (2020a, b) on certainty; Hawthorne and Logins (2021), Fassio and Logins (2023), and Logins (2023) on justification; and Siscoe (2021a, b), (2022a, b), and (2023) on rationality.

  29. Even though I have spoken here strictly in terms of knowledge, if we instead suppose that the New View is correct, Overnight Rain can still be used as an example of degrees of ignorance. Rebecca truly believes that it rained last night, while Sarah merely believes that it might have rained, making Sarah more ignorant than Rebecca that it rained last night.

  30. Like before, Overnight Rain* can be adapted to make comparative judgments on the New View as well. If we suppose that Rebecca assigns a high credence to it raining overnight while Sarah assigns that proposition a low credence, then Rebecca comes closer than Sarah to truly believing that p.

  31. See Brogaard (2016), p. 57.

  32. See Boteach (2016) and Molefe (2015).

  33. See Brogaard (2016), p. 69.

  34. Ibid.

  35. For more on how semantic accounts attempt to represent the Sorites, see Graff Fara (2000), Kennedy (2007), Pinkal (1995), and Rusiecki (1985).

  36. See Brogaard (2016), p. 70.

  37. See Sorensen (1987), pp. 769–700.

References

  • Areddy, J. (2010). WikiLeaks: China profits off cheap Venezuelan oil. Wall Street Journal. https://www.wsj.com/articles/BL-CJB-12223

  • Bamford, J. (2005). A pretext for war. Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, C. (2002). The dynamics of vagueness. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, M. (2016). Justification, excuse, and the exculpatory power of ignorance. In R. Peels & M. Blaauw (Eds.), Perspectives on ignorance from moral and social philosophy (pp. 65–88). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartsch, R., & Venneman, T. (1972). The grammar of relative adjectives and comparison. Linguistische Berichte, 20, 19–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beddor, B. (2020a). Certainty in action. The Philosophical Quarterly, 70(281), 711–737.

  • Beddor, B. (2020b). New work for certainty. Philosophers’ Imprint, 20(8), 1–25.

  • Bianculli, D. (2020). Best TV of 2020. National Public Radio. https://www.npr.org/2020/12/24/949549411/best-tv-of-2020-great-shows-brought-us-together-in-a-difficult-distanced-year

  • Bierwisch, M. (1989). The semantics of gradation. In M. Bierwisch & E. Lang (Eds.), Dimensional adjectives (pp. 71–261). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann, M. (2016). Ignorance and epistemic contextualism. In R. Peels & M. Blaauw (Eds.), The epistemic dimensions of ignorance. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boteach, S. (2016). Feeling burned by Bernie on Israel. The Observer. https://observer.com/2016/04/feeling-burned-by-bernie-on-israel/

  • Brogaard, B. (2016). Ignorance and Incompetence: Linguistic considerations. In R. Peels & M. Blaauw (Eds.), The epistemic dimensions of ignorance. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnett, H. (2014). A delineation solution to the puzzles of absolute adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 37, 1–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnett, H. (2017). Gradability in natural language: Logical and grammatical foundations. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bylinina, L. (2012). Functional standards and the absolute/relative distinction. Proceedings of Sinn Und Bedeutung, 16(1), 141–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, G. 2018. Fire during the construction phase of a project. Linkedin Articles. https://www.linkedin.com/pulse/fire-during-construction-phase-project-graeme-clark-miet-techiosh/?articleId=6414557495192358912

  • Craig, M. (1998). Kundun: A biography of the family of the Dalai Lama. Counterpoint.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, M. (1977). The semantics of degree. In B. Partee (Ed.), Montague grammar (pp. 261–292). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 40, 363–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunning, D. (2016). The psychological quirk that explains why you love Donald Trump. Politico https://www.politico.com/magazine/story/2016/05/donald-trump-supporters-dunning-kruger-effect-213904/

  • Fassio, D., & Logins, A. (2023). Justification and gradability. Philosophical Studies, 180, 2051–2077.

  • Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth, and logic. Synthese, 30, 265–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2018). Ignorance of ignorance. Synthese, 195, 4031–4045.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, W. J. (2008). Moral responsibility and normative ignorance: Answering a new skeptical challenge. Ethics, 118, 589–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2016). Epistemic Injustice and the Preservation of Ignorance. In R. Peels & M. Blaauw (Eds.), The epistemic dimensions of ignorance (pp. 160–177). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1999). Knowledge in a social world. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A., & Olsson, E. (2009). Reliabilism and the value of knowledge. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic value. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graff Fara, D. (2000). Shifting sands: An interest-relative theory of vagueness. Philosophical Topics, 20, 45–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero, A. (2007). Don’t know, don’t kill: Moral ignorance, culpability, and caution. Philosophical Studies, 136, 59–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J., & Logins, A. (2021). Graded epistemic justification. Philosophical Studies, 178, 1845–1858.

  • Hetherington, S. (2001). Good knowledge, bad knowledge: On two dogmas of epistemology. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2011). How to know: A practicalist conception of knowledge. John Wiley and Sons.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hooke, P. (2021). Dating with a disability is like entering a lottery that you know you’ll never win. MamaMia. https://www.mamamia.com.au/dating-with-a-disability/

  • Husak, D. (2016). Ignorance of law: A philosophical inquiry. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husak, D., & Callender, C. (2010). Willful ignorance, knowledge, and the ‘equal culpability’ thesis: A study of the deeper significance of the principle of legality. In D. Husak (Ed.), The philosophy of criminal law: Selected essays (pp. 200–232). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, M. (2017). Anti-welsh language complaints at restaurant ‘on a daily basis’. North Wales News. https://www.dailypost.co.uk/news/north-wales-news/anti-welsh-language-complaints-restaurant-13245894

  • Kamp, H. (1975). Two theories of adjectives. In E. Keenan (Ed.), Formal semantics of natural language (pp. 123–155). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Keertana. (2012). Year of the classics. The Readventurer. http://www.thereadventurer.com/-home/year-of-the-classics-keertana-from-ivy-book-bindings-talks-about-her-love-of-gone-with-the-wind

  • Kelly, E. (2012). What is an excuse? In D. J. Coates & N. Tognazzini (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 244–262). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. (2007). Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(1), 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C., & McNally, L. (2005). Scale structure and the semantic typology of gradable predicates. Language, 81(2), 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, E. (1980). A semantics for positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4, 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, A., & Morreau, M. (2000). Fitting words: Vague language in context. Linguistics and Philosophy, 23, 577–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kyle, B. (2021). Truth and ignorance. Synthese, 198, 7739–7762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P. (2011a). Knowledge, ignorance, and true belief. Theoria, 77, 309–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P. (2011b). On ignorance: A reply to peels. Philosophia, 39, 335–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P. (2012). On ignorance: A vindication of the standard view. Philosophia, 40, 379–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P. (2013). Why the standard view of ignorance prevails. Philosophia, 41, 239–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P. (2019). When ignorance excuses. Ratio, 32, 22–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P., & Peels, R. (2016). The nature of ignorance: Two views. In R. Peels & M. Blaauw (Eds.), The epistemic dimensions of ignorance. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese, 22, 18–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logins, A. (2023). The paradox of graded justification. Episteme, 1–29.

  • Lynch, K. (2016). Willful ignorance and self-deception. Philosophical Studies, 173, 505–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meylan, A. (2020). Ignorance and its disvalue. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 97, 433–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meylan, A. (2024). In defence of the normative account of ignorance. Erkenntnis, 89, 207–221.

  • Molefe, M. (2015). Shakes must tone down on Paranoia. Sowetan Live. https://www.sowetanlive.co.za/sport/2015-03-27-shakes-must-tone-down-on-paranoia/

  • Nottelmann, N. (2016). The varieties of ignorance. In R. Peels & M. Blaauw (Eds.), The epistemic dimensions of ignorance. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E., & Proietti, C. (2016). Explicating ignorance and doubt: A possible worlds approach. In R. Peels & M. Blaauw (Eds.), The epistemic dimensions of ignorance. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peels, R. (2010). What is ignorance? Philosophia, 38, 57–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peels, R. (2011). Ignorance is lack of true belief: A rejoinder to Le Morvan. Philosophia, 39, 344–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peels, R. (2012). The new view on ignorance undefeated. Philosophia, 40, 741–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peels, R. (2014). What kind of ignorance excuses? Two neglected issues. The Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 478–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piedrahita, O. (2021). Lucky ignorance, modality, and lack of knowledge. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. Online First.

  • Pinkal, M. (1995). Logic and lexicon. Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piovarchy, A. (2021). Responsibility for testimonial injustice. Philosophical Studies, 178, 597–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2021a). Ignorance and inquiry. American Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 111–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2021b). Ignorance and normativity. Philosophical Topics, 49, 225–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robichaud, P. (2014). On Culpable ignorance and Akrasia. Ethics, 125, 137–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2003). Culpability and ignorance. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 103, 61–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rotstein, C., & Winter, Y. (2004). Total adjectives vs. partial adjectives: Scale structure and higher-order modifiers. Natural Language Semantics, 12, 259–288.

  • Rusiecki, J. (1985). On adjectives and comparisons in English. Longman Linguistics Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sapir, E. (1944). Grading: A study in semantics. Philosophy of Science, 11, 93–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarch, A. (2018). Willful ignorance in law and morality. Philosophy Compass, 13, e12490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarch, A. (2019). Criminally ignorant: Why the law pretends we know what we don’t. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sedivy, J., Tanenhaus, M., Chambers, C., & Carlson, G. (1999). Achieving incremental semantic interpretation through contextual representations. Cognition, 71, 109–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silva, P., & Siscoe, R. W. (2024). Ignorance and awareness. Noûs, 58(1), 225–243.

  • Siscoe, R. W. (2021a). Belief, rational and justified. Mind, 130(517), 59–83.

  • Siscoe, R. W. (2021b). Does being rational require being ideally rational? Philosophical Topics, 49(2), 245–266.

  • Siscoe, R. W. (2022a). Rational supererogation and epistemic permissivism. Philosophical Studies, 179(2), 571–591.

  • Siscoe, R. W. (2022b). Real and ideal rationality. Philosophical Studies, 179(3), 879–910.

  • Siscoe, R. W. (2023). Being rational enough: Maximizing, satisficing, and degrees of rationality. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 101(1), 111–127.

  • Smith, H. (1983). Culpable ignorance. The Philosophical Review, 92, 543–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solt, S. (2012). Comparison to arbitrary standards. Proceedings of Sinn Und Bedeutung, 16(2), 557–570.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (1987). The vagueness of knowledge. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17, 767–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2001). Human knowledge, animal and reflective. Philosophical Studies, 106, 193–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2009). Knowing full well: The normativity of beliefs as performances. Philosophical Studies, 142, 5–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2011). Knowing full well. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2004). On the linguistic basis for contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 119–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Syrett, K., Bradley, E., Kennedy, C., & Lidz, J. 2006. Shifting standards: Children’s understanding of gradable adjectives. In Proceedings of the inaugural conference on generative approaches to language acquisition (pp. 353–364).

  • Syrett, K., Kennedy, C., & Lidz, J. (2010). Meaning and context in children’s understanding of gradable adjectives. Journal of Semantics, 27, 1–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1975). Ignorance: A case for scepticism. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Usher, N. (2014). Making news at the New York times. University of Michigan Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Woudenberg, R. (2009). Ignorance and force: Two excusing conditions for false beliefs. American Philosophical Quarterly, 46, 373–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, S. (1972). Attributives and their modifiers. Nous, 6(4), 310–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wieland, J. W. (2017). Willful ignorance. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20, 105–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, M. (1988). An essay on moral responsibility. Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, M. (2008). Living with uncertainty: The moral significance of ignorance. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, M. (2020). Willful ignorance and moral responsibility. In M. Timmons (Ed.), Oxford studies in normative ethics. (Vol. 10). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert Weston Siscoe.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

For feedback on previous iterations of this paper, I am grateful to Sven Bernecker, Michael Blome-Tillmann, Pierre Le Morvan, Rik Peels, Oscar Piedrahita, Duncan Pritchard, Paul Silva, Christopher Willard-Kyle, and an audience at CONCEPT at the University of Cologne.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Siscoe, R.W. Knowledge, true belief, and the gradability of ignorance. Philos Stud 181, 893–916 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02119-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02119-5

Keywords

Navigation